The directory «Plots»
Aristotle (Αριστοτέλης)
(384–322 B.C.)
Greek philosopher, b. Stagira. He is sometimes called the Stagirite.
Aristotle’s father, Nicomachus, was a noted physician. Aristotle studied (367–347 B.C.) under Plato at the Academy and there wrote many dialogues that were praised for their eloquence. Only fragments of these dialogues are extant. He tutored (342–c.339 B.C.) Alexander the Great at the Macedonian court, left to live in Stagira, and then returned to Athens. In 335 B.C. he opened a school in the Lyceum; some distinguished members of the Academy followed him. His practice of lecturing in the Lyceum’s portico, or covered walking place (peripatos), gave his school the name Peripatetic. During the anti-Macedonian agitation after Alexander’s death, Aristotle fled in 323 B.C. to Chalcis, where he died.
Aristotle’s extant writings consist largely of his written versions of his lectures; some passages appear to be interpolations of notes made by his students; the texts were edited and given their present form by Andronicus of Rhodes in the 1st cent. B.C. Chief among them are the Organum, consisting of six treatises on logic; Physics; Metaphysics; De Anima [on the soul]; Nicomachean Ethics and Eudemian Ethics; De Poetica [poetics]; Rhetoric; and a series of works on biology and physics. In the late 19th cent. his Constitution of Athens, an account of Athenian government, was found.
Aristotle placed great emphasis in his school on direct observation of nature, and in science he taught that theory must follow fact. He considered philosophy to be the discerning of the self-evident, changeless first principles that form the basis of all knowledge. Logic was for Aristotle the necessary tool of any inquiry, and the syllogism was the sequence that all logical thought follows. He introduced the notion of category into logic and taught that reality could be classified according to several categories—substance (the primary category), quality, quantity, relation, determination in time and space, action, passion or passivity, position, and condition.
Aristotle also taught that knowledge of a thing, beyond its classification and description, requires an explanation of causality, or why it is. He posited four causes or principles of explanation: the material cause (the substance of which the thing is made); the formal cause (its design); the efficient cause (its maker or builder); and the final cause (its purpose or function). In modern thought the efficient cause is generally considered the central explanation of a thing, but for Aristotle the final cause had primacy.
He used this account of causes to examine the relation of form to matter, and in his conclusions differed sharply from those of his teacher, Plato. Aristotle believed that a form, with the exception of the Prime Mover, or God, had no separate existence, but rather was immanent in matter. Thus, in the Aristotelian system, form and matter together constitute concrete individual realities; the Platonic system holds that a concrete reality partakes of a form (the ideal) but does not embody it. Aristotle believed that form caused matter to move and defined motion as the process by which the potentiality of matter (the thing itself) became the actuality of form (motion itself). He held that the Prime Mover alone was pure form and as the “unmoved mover” and final cause was the goal of all motion.
Aristotle’s ethical theory reflects his metaphysics. Following Plato, he argued that the goodness or virtue of a thing lay in the realization of its specific nature. The highest good for humans is the complete and habitual exercise of the specifically human function—rationality. Rationality is exercised through the practice of two kinds of virtue, moral and intellectual. Aristotle emphasized the traditional Greek notion of moral virtue as the mean between extremes. Well-being (eudaemonia) is the pursuit not of pleasure (hedonism) but rather of the Good, a composite ideal, consisting of contemplation (the intellectual life) and, subordinate to that, engagement in politics (the moral life). In the Politics, Aristotle holds that, by nature, humans form political associations, and he explores the best forms these may take. For Aristotle’s aesthetic views, which are set forth in the Poetics, see tragedy.
After the decline of Rome, Aristotle’s work was lost in the West. However, in the 9th cent., Arab scholars introduced Aristotle to Islam, and Muslim theology, philosophy, and natural science all took on an Aristotelian cast. It was largely through Arab and Jewish scholars that Aristotelian thought was reintroduced in the West. His works became the basis of medieval scholasticism; much of Roman Catholic theology shows, through St. Thomas Aquinas, Aristotelian influence. There has also been a revival of Aristotelian influence on philosophy in the 20th cent. His teleological approach has continued to be central to biology, but it was banished from physics by the scientific revolution of the 17th cent. His work in astronomy, later elaborated by Ptolemy, was controverted by the investigations of Copernicus and Galileo.
Ajman, 1972, The School of Athens
Ajman, 1972, The School of Athens
Ajman, 1972, The School of Athens
Belgium, 1932, Mercier with busts of Aristotle
Belgium, 1932, Mercier with busts of Aristotle
Comoren Islands, 1977, Nobel prize winners
Cyprus, 1978, Bust of Aristotle
Gibraltar, 2009, Aristotle
Greece, 1956, Aristotle
Greece, 1978, Bust of Aristotle
Greece, 1978, The School of Athens
Greece, 1978, Map of Chalkididiki and statue plinth
Greece, 1978, Aristotle the Wise (Bysantine fresco)
Greece, 1992, Bust of Aristotle and Makedonia
Grenada Grenadines, 1993, Aristotle with the Bust of Homer
Guinea, 2007, Tony Estanguet, Aristotle
Guinea, 2009, Aristotle, Goethe
Korea Nord, 1983, The School of Athens
Liberia, 1973, Aristotle, Ptolemy and Copernicus
Mali, 1978, Aristotle
Manama, 1972, Aristotle with the Bust of Homere
Mexico, 1978, Aristotle
Mexico, 1978, Statue of Aristotle
Redonda, 1987, Aristotle
Sao Tome e Principe, 2008, Naturalists
Sierra Leone, 1983, The School of Athens
Spain, 1986, Aristotle
Uruguay, 1996, Aristotle
Vatican, 1997, Aristotle describing the Species
YAR, 1968, The School of Athens
Greece, 1978.07.10, Athens. Aristotle